24 August 2007

Knowing and Following Jesus

I've just recently finished preaching a five-week series entitled "Knowing and Following Jesus." You can find mp3s and Powerpoint slides here: http://orc.typepad.com/sunday_series/.

25 July 2007

Of Red Herrings and Straw Men—A Reply to Steven Carr

On 07 May 2007 I posted my term paper for a Metaphysics course I took as part of my on-going studies in philosophy. The paper, entitled Plantinga and the Problem of Evil dealt with Dr. Alvin Plantinga’s celebrated solution to the logical problem of evil. While most philosophers acknowledge Plantinga’s Free Will Defense as a successful reply to the problem, there are dissenting voices. My professor is one those dissenters, so I thought that it would be an enjoyable challenge to analyze both Plantinga’s Free Will Defense, and one of my professor’s essays on the subject. My essay, which you can find here, was the result of that work. My post went unanswered for a little over two months—and to be honest, I never expected anyone to make any comments. To my pleasant surprise, a Mr Steven Carr did just that on 16 July. Mr Carr’s comments can be found at the end of the link above. Here are Mr Carr’s comments:

--------------------------------------------------------------------------
Steven Carr said...

“Now consider some state of affairs S such that in S Curley is offered—but has not accepted or rejected—a bribe. Obviously there are a great many possible worlds that include S—and in at least one of these Curley is significantly free but does no moral wrong.”

There are two possible worlds.

Let us assume God exists.

So Curley is in a situation S, which situation includes an omniscient God who infallibly knows that Curley will refuse the bribe.

If you believe in libertarian free will, there is also a situation S-prime, which is identical to S, except for one thing - the contents of God's knowledge. In S-prime , God infallibly knows that Curley will accept the bribe.

Now Plantinga declare it a fact that in both of those worlds, Curley will refuse the bribe.

This is obviously false.

The statement “God knows that if Curley is offered a bribe, he will freely choose to accept it,” is a plainly false statement. It contradicts Plantinga's libertarian free will assumptions that there are two identical worlds, differing only in the contents of God's knowledge (a world where we choose right in situation S and a world where we choose wrong)

God can actualise eithe of those two worlds. The situation is entirely symmetrical between good and evil.

If PLantinga says Curley is not significantly free in either of them, then that is a fault in his definition of an omniscient God.

“If he had, S would be actual, and Curley would have gone wrong and taken the bribe (for remember, God knows that if Curley is offered a bribe, he will freely accept it)”

God does not know that. Plantinga is pulling the wool over people's eyes.

Libertarian free will (if true), means there is a world where the counterfactual of freedom is that Curley will refuse the bribe.

Steven Carr said...

It is Christian dogma that God can, and has , created beings with free will that he knew in advance would never choose evil.

Nor does Plantinga's Molinism work (although Molinism is trivially true, granted libertarian free will and an omniscient God).

If it is part of the essence of me, that I choose evil when placed in some situations that occur in this world, then logically God can create a near-identical twin of me.

This twin behaves just like me, except on one or two occasions when I choose evil and he chooses good.

There is nothing to prevent God creating near-identical twins. My near-identical twin does not even have to be perfect. There could be circumstances in which I choose good and he chooses evil. Provided those circumstances are not actualised (and God doesn't have to actualise *every* circumstance I could logically find myself in), then there would be no problem.

So Plantinga's argument is shot to pieces.

Steven Carr said...

“Clearly there is some possible world in which Curley freely rejects the bribe—there is even at least one in which he does no moral wrong at all (and Plantinga acknowledges this). But if God actualizes that world, even weakly, Curley’s transworld depravity will be “triggered”: his S will be actual and he will go wrong with respect to his A.”

This is all just incoherent.

If the world is *defined* as being the world in which Curley refuses the bribe, then Curley will refuse the bribe.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------

While I appreciate Mr Carr’s attention to my blog, I must admit that I do not find his objections to my essay to be formidable. To be frank, I cannot find a single unifying thread running through his replies, so I am forced to reply to what I take to be his main themes.

Steven Carr, Reply One—Libertarian Freedom and Red Herrings
In his first reply, Mr Carr attacks Plantinga’s argument because of the latter's commitment to “libertarian free will.” Carr thinks that the statement, “God knows that if Curley is offered a bribe, he will freely choose to accept it” is “plainly false.” Carr thinks that the Plantinga’s commitment to libertarian free will commits him to the idea that there are only two possible worlds, one in which human beings do right and one in which humans do wrong in some situation S (which he does not define beyond God’s knowledge of Curley’s actions). Now God, Carr thinks, can actualize either of these worlds.

Unfortunately for Mr Carr's case, all this is a mere red herring. Plantinga’s Free Will Defense certainly assumes some form of libertarian freedom. But it is not clear that this undermines his free will defense. Certainly the argument includes the premise that human beings are significantly morally free (by which Plantinga means that human beings are free with respect to their actions, and that those actions are not causally determined). This may or may not be the case; but for the purposes of Plantinga’s argument libertarian freedom need only be possible—and it certainly seems to be possible. To defeat Plantinga's argument, Carr would have to show that libertarian freedom isn't even possible; and he's hardly accomplished that.

Furthermore, Mr Carr makes the assertion that if libertarian freedom obtains, then there are only two possible worlds. It is not at all clear how these two possible worlds differ—at one point Carr says they differ in terms of the contents of God’s knowledge; at another, that one is the world where human beings “choose right” in S and one in which they choose wrong (though note that Carr did not stipulate that all human beings are included in S nor even that S is a part of both possible worlds). In any event, it hardly matters how Carr characterizes the two worlds, because his basic assertion—that libertarian freedom entails that there are only two possible worlds—is false. Libertarian free will is the view that human beings aren’t constrained in any way with respect to their moral choices, that every moral choice is completely freely chosen by a moral agent, and not determined by any causal factors other than the agent’s own volition. Carr thinks that this entails that there are only two possible worlds. But it is not at all clear that such entailment obtains! If Mr Carr wants to claim that libertarian freedom is incompatible with Plantinga’s free will defense, he is going to have to justify the claim that libertarian freedom entails only two possible worlds, because it is far from clear just why libertarian freedom would constrain the number and nature of possible worlds. In fact, it seems to me that just the opposite is the case.

Consider the case of Adam, a tourist in Las Vegas. Adam is playing blackjack; Bill is his dealer, and Charlie is playing the position to Adam’s left. During play, just as Charlie is pulling out his wallet to pay for more chips, Bill has a heart attack. Charlie, a medical doctor, abandons his wallet on the table, and rushes to Bill’s aid. This leaves Adam with at least four choices that I can see. (1) He can steal Bill’s wallet and leave. (2) He can steal the chips on the table and leave. (3) He can steal the chips and the wallet and leave. (4) He can ignore the chips and the wallet, and call for help. If one subscribes to libertarian freedom, all choices are possible for Adam. His will is not constrained in any way with respect to what choice he will make. So it seems to be the case that there are not just two possible worlds but four: one in which Adam chooses (1), one in which he chooses (2), and likewise for (3) and (4). And when one considers how very many choices all the people in the world have to make, and how very many options they face in making those decisions, it seems clear that there are far, far more possible worlds than the two that Mr Carr proposes--to say nothing of the possible worlds in which there are no people at all!

Mr Carr makes much of the implications of libertarian free will; but libertarian freedom does not have the entailments that he thinks it does! Either Mr Carr misunderstands the implications of libertarian freedom, or he misunderstands the role of freedom of will in Plantinga’s free will defense, or he has a fundamental misunderstanding of the concept of possible worlds. In any event his analysis of all three is wrong, so his first reply hardly presents a problem to Plantinga’s solution to the logical problem of evil.

Carr might be able to attack libertarian freedom in order to undermine Plantinga’s argument. In order to do that, he will have to come to an accurate understanding of libertarian free will. But over and above this, Plantinga doesn’t need his argument to be true—he only needs it to be possibly true. So if Mr Carr is to employ an attack on libertarian freedom in an effort to refute Plantinga’s Free Will Defense, he will have to show not only that libertarianism is false, but that it is necessarily false—that it is, that it is not even possibly true.

It turns out that all this is a red herring—Mr Carr employs a scattershot approach to defeating Plantinga’s argument in which he makes grand assertions (“This is obviously false”) and dubious claims (“Libertarian free will (if true) means there is a world where the counterfactual of freedom is that Curley will refuse the bribe”) which do not actually address Plantinga’s argument, but which only serve to distract from the issue at hand. But let us not allow Mr Carr to distract us from what is at issue: Plantinga’s Free Will Defense.

Steven Carr Reply Two—Red Herring, Meet Straw Man
Again, Mr Carr employs the same scattershot approach in this reply that characterized his first. His hope is that one of his many claims (which, conveniently, are left to stand as mere propositions for which he does not offer any substantive arguments) will score against Plantinga's argument. Mr Carr even presumes to describe Christian beliefs; he claims that “It is Christian dogma that God can, and has , created beings with free will that he knew in advance would never choose evil.” Curiously, this claim is not at all familiar to me, despite my many, many years of Christian faith; perhaps I should have been reading the Gospel According to Steven Carr! In any event, Mr Carr does make one near argument in this reply, one which revolves around the ability of God to create near-identical twins.

“If it is part of the essence of me,” Carr says, “that I choose evil when placed in some situations that occur in this world, then logically God can create a near-identical twin of me.” Now, in the first place it is not at all clear that the inclusion of free will in a human’s essential nature is sufficient for knowing that God has the ability to create a near-identical twin of some person. Perhaps it is the case that freedom of will is part of the essential nature of human beings but that there is no God! It certainly seems possible for that to be the case. And if it were, the inclusion of freedom in human nature wouldn’t say anything at all about God! So right from the start, Carr’s argument stands on shaky ground, being based on so questionable a conditional as he has given us.

But let us grant that God has this ability for the sake of further inquiry. Carr says that this twin behaves exactly like him except on the “one or two” occasions in which Carr does wrong. On those occasions, twin-Carr chooses good. But Carr goes further, asserting that on the occasions where he chooses good, twin-Carr chooses evil.

Now suppose that twin-Carr exists in possible world W and suppose that the actual world and W are identical in every respect except for the fact that Carr and twin-Carr’s moral behavior are mirror opposites. Whenever Carr chooses evil, twin-Carr chooses good and vice versa. I am willing to grant all this because this has absolutely no bearing on Plantinga’s Free Will Defense. Plantinga’s basic assertion is that it is possible that God could not have created a world with moral good but no more evil. And it is not clear how Carr and twin-Carr will disprove such an assertion. Carr has as much as admitted that there are “one or two occasions” in which he chooses evil. So if God actualizes the world in which Carr exists (that is, the actual world) there will be evil in the world (at the very least the amount that results from Carr’s evil choices, however modest). So if God actualizes that world, there will be evil in the world, and it will not have been shown that God could create a world with moral good but no moral evil. But suppose that God had actualized W, the world containing twin-Carr. If he had done that, there would still have been moral evil in the world. Remember, twin-Carr’s moral behavior is a mirror opposite from Carr’s—which means that there are only “one or two” occasions in which twin-Carr chooses moral good. Which obviously means that every other of twin-Carr’s decisions are for moral evil. And that means that twin-Carr will bring about moral evil. And that means that if God actualizes W, it will be a world that contains moral evil. And so Mr Carr has still not shown that it is possible for God to actualize a world with moral good but no moral evil.

Mr Carr thinks that to get around these problems, all God has to do is not actualize the particular circumstances in which he chooses evil. But he fundamentally misunderstands the nature of world-actualization (as Plantinga characterizes it). Plantinga thinks that God actualizes the initial conditions of the world, and that human beings complete that world by their own free choices (and if he had read my essay thoroughly, he would not be confused on this point). It is not that God actualizes particular circumstances—he actualizes particular worlds. Now, given this objection, Carr’s counter-argument would be that God should actualize the world in which he chooses to do no moral wrong. But if he did, that would betray a fundamental misunderstanding of my essay, because that is just the objection that I argue against in my essay. If Plantinga is right that transworld depravity is possible, then it might turn out that God can’t create a world with moral good but no moral evil.

As it happens, disposing of transworld depravity would have gone quite a good distance toward defeating Plantinga’s Free Will Defense. But again, Mr Carr has declined to actually engage with Plantinga’s argument. This time Carr has erected a straw man—Carr spends his time establishing the fact that God can create a moral-twin Carr; but Plantinga never discussed the making of moral twins! So establishing the fact that God could make a twin-Carr does absolutely nothing to defeat Plantinga’s argument. The grandiose claim “Plantinga’s argument is shot to pieces” is clearly not warranted. Plantinga wants to establish that it is possible that God could not have created a world with moral good but no moral evil. Mr Carr has successfully shown that God could have created a moral-twin Carr, but this in no way shows that it is not possible that God could not have created a world with moral good but no moral evil. So once again, Mr Carr has failed to produce an argument that will defeat Plantinga’s Free Will Defense.

Steven Carr Reply Three—Incoherent Indeed
In his third reply Mr Carr abandons his scattershot strategy (thankfully) but does not come any closer to defeating Plantinga.

Carr quotes two sentences from my essay, from my concluding reply to Geirsson and Losonsky. The quoted section deals with the issue of transworld depravity—which is what prevents God from creating a world without any moral good. If Mr Carr had thoroughly read my essay he would have understood the role and significance of transworld depravity. Instead, the only counter-argument he can offer is this: “This is all incoherent.” I submit that if Carr thinks that my summary of Plantinga’s argument is “incoherent” it is not due to error on my part. Transworld depravity is a simple matter of conditionals: if such and such happens, this and that will be the result. Not at all incoherent, unless one is so committed to one’s position that one cannot even comprehend the arguments of one’s opponents. In any event, the professor who graded the essay (who, incidentally, is not a fan of Plantinga) found it coherent enough to give me an “A.” That being the case, I’m rather inclined to accept his judgment of the matter over Mr Carr’s. Of course, this reply leaves me open to the fallacy of argument to authority, and that would be right. So I will say instead that there is a difference between an argument’s being logically inconsistent and an argument’s being difficult to understand. And Mr Carr’s failure to properly understand Plantinga’s argument from Transworld Depravity is hardly a winning critique of Plantinga’s argument. I suggest that had Mr Carr spent more time studying Plantinga, he might have actually offered an argument against Transworld Depravity, instead of making the bald assertion that it is inconsistent.

Carr claims, “If the world is *defined* as being the world in which Curley refuses the bribe, then Crley will refuse the bribe.” But nothing in Plantinga’s argument suggests that world-definition is what is at stake here. Plantinga never makes the claim that some possible world is defined as the world in which Curley accepts or refuses the bribe. He merely says that in some worlds Curley freely chooses to accept the bribe, and in some to refuse it. That choice is a feature of those possible worlds but Plantinga never claimed that that was what defined those worlds. Again, this is a straw man (though a poorly developed one). But no matter: transworld depravity can settle this issue. Suppose that in possible world W' Curley is offered a bribe and chooses to refuse it. In that world, Curley suffers from transworld depravity—that is, in W' Curley does no wrong (including refusing the bribe). But because he suffers from transworld depravity, if W' were the actual world, Curley would go wrong with respect to the bribe. Thus it would turn out that God hadn't actualized W' at all--because Curley's choosing to reject the bribe is a feature of W', and if Curley accepts it, the world that has been actualized can't be W'.

Transworld Depravity Triumphant
And therein lies the power of transworld depravity. If a person suffers from transworld depravity, there is no way for God to actualize a world with no moral evil because any attempt to actualize such a world would activate transworld depravity—and then moral evil would have been brought into the world and it would turn out not to be a world with no moral evil. And most importantly, transworld depravity doesn’t have to be true—it only has to be possible. If transworld depravity is even possible, then Plantinga has established that it is possible that God could not create a world in which there is moral good but no moral evil.

Although I applaud Mr Carr for engaging in discussion around this issue, I must conclude that his attempt to defeat Plantinga’s Free Will Defense is utterly unsuccessful.

18 May 2007

Philosophical Humor

Found this at Michael Huemer's website. For those non-philosophers out there, this is the kind of stuff we find hilarious.

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Consider the following case:

A brain in a vat on Twin Earth is at the wheel of a runaway trolley. There are only two options that the brain can take: the right side of the fork in the track or the left side of the fork. There is no way in sight of derailing or stopping the trolley and the brain is aware of this, for the brain knows trolleys. The brain is causally hooked up to the trolley such that the brain can determine the course which the trolley will take.

On the right side of the track there is a single railroad worker, Jones, who will definitely be killed if the brain steers the trolley to the right. If the railman on the right lives, he will go on to kill five men for the sake of killing them, but in doing so will inadvertently save the lives of thirty orphans (one of the five men he will kill is planning to destroy a bridge that the orphan's bus will be crossing later that night). One of the orphans that will be killed would have grown up to become a tyrant who would make good utilitarian men do bad things. Another of the orphans would grow up to become G.E.M. Anscombe, while a third would invent the pop-top can.

If the brain in the vat chooses the left side of the track, the trolley will definitely hit and kill a railman on the left side of the track, "Leftie" and will hit and destroy ten beating hearts on the track that could (and would) have been transplanted into ten patients in the local hospital that will die without donor hearts. These are the only hearts available, and the brain is aware of this, for the brain knows hearts. If the railman on the left side of the track lives, he too will kill five men, in fact the same five that the railman on the right would kill. However, "Leftie" will kill the five as an unintended consequence of saving ten men: he will inadvertently kill the five men rushing the ten hearts to the local hospital for transplantation. A further result of "Leftie's" act would be that the busload of orphans will be spared. Among the five men killed by "Leftie" are both the man responsible for putting the brain at the controls of the trolley, and the author of this example. If the ten hearts and "Leftie" are killed by the trolley, the ten prospective heart-transplant patients will die and their kidneys will be used to save the lives of twenty kidney-transplant patients, one of whom will grow up to cure cancer, and one of whom will grow up to be Hitler. There are other kidneys and dialysis machines available, however the brain does not know kidneys, and this is not a factor.

Assume that the brain's choice, whatever it turns out to be, will serve as an example to other brains-in-vats and so the effects of his decision will be amplified. Also assume that if the brain chooses the right side of the fork, an unjust war free of war crimes will ensue, while if the brain chooses the left fork, a just war fraught with war crimes will result. Furthermore, there is an intermittently active Cartesian demon deceiving the brain in such a manner that the brain is never sure if it is being deceived.

QUESTION: What should the brain do?

[ALTERNATIVE EXAMPLE: Same as above, except the brain has had a commisurotomy, and the left half of the brain is a consequentialist and the right side is an absolutist.]

© 1988 by the American Philosophical Association

14 May 2007

Followers and Admirers

From Provocations, by Søren Kierkegaard, pages 85-88

---------------------------------------------------------------------------

It is well known that Christ consistently used the expression “follower.” He never asks for admirers, worshippers, or adherents. No, he calls disciples. It is not adherents of a teaching but followers of a life Christ is looking for.

Christ understood that being a “disciple” was in innermost and deepest harmony with what he said about himself. Christ claimed to be the way and the truth and the life (Jn. 14:6). For this reason, he could never be satisfied with adherents who accepted his teaching – especially with those who in their lives ignored it or let things take their usual course. His whole life on earth, from beginning to end, was destined solely to have followers and to make admirers impossible.

Christ came into the world with the purpose of saving, not instructing it. At the same time – as is implied in his saving work – he came to be the pattern, to leave footprints for the person who would join him, who would become a follower. This is why Christ was born and lived and died in lowliness. It is absolutely impossible for anyone to sneak away from the Pattern with excuse and evasion on the basis that It, after all, possessed earthly and worldly advantages that he did not have. In that sense, to admire Christ is the false invention of a later age, aided by the presumption of “loftiness.” No, there is absolutely nothing to admire in Jesus, unless you want to admire poverty, misery, and contempt.

What then, is the difference between an admirer and a follower? A follower is or strives to be what he admires. An admirer, however, keeps himself personally detached. He fails to see that what is admired involves a claim upon him, and thus he fails to be or strive to be what he admires.

To want to admire instead of to follow Christ is not necessarily an invention by bad people. No, it is more an invention by those who spinelessly keep themselves detached, who keep themselves at a safe distance. Admirers are related to the admired only through the excitement of the imagination. To them he is like an actor on the stage except that, this being real life, the effect he produces is somewhat stronger. But for their part, admirers make the same demands that are made in the theater: to sit safe and calm. Admirers are only all too willing to serve Christ as long as proper caution is exercised, lest one personally come in contact with danger. As such, they refuse to accept that Christ’s life is a demand. In actual fact, they are offended at him. His radical, bizarre character so offends them that when they honestly see Christ for who he is, they are no longer able to experience the tranquility they so much seek after. They know full well that to associate with him too closely amounts to being up for examination. Even though he “says nothing” against them personally, they know that his life tacitly judges theirs.
And Christ’s life indeed makes it manifest, terrifyingly manifest, what dreadful untruth it is to admire the truth instead of following it. When there is no danger, when there is a dead calm, when everything is favorable to our Christianity, it is all too easy to confuse an admirer with a follower. And this can happen very quietly. The admirer can be in the delusion that the position he takes is the true one, when all he is doing is playing it safe. Give heed, therefore, to the call of discipleship!

Now suppose that there is no longer any special danger, as it no doubt is in so many of our Christian countries, bound up with publicly confessing Christ. Suppose there is no longer need to journey in the night. The difference between following and admiring – between being, or at least striving to be – still remains. Forget about this danger connected with confessing Christ and think rather of the real danger which is inescapably bound up with being a Christian. Does not the Way – Christ’s requirement to die to the world, to forgo the worldly, and his requirement of self-denial – does this not contain enough danger? If Christ’s commandment were to be obeyed, would they not constitute a danger? Would they not be sufficient to manifest the difference between an admirer and a follower?

The difference between an admirer and a follower still remains, no matter where you are. The admirer never makes any true sacrifices. He always plays it safe. Though in words, phrases, songs, he is inexhaustible about how highly he prizes Christ, he renounces nothing, gives up nothing, will not reconstruct his life, will not be what he admires, and will not let his life express what it is he supposedly admires. Not so for the follower. No, no. The follower aspires with all his strength, with all his will to be what he admires. And then, remarkably enough, even though he is living amongst a “Christian people,” the same danger results for him as was once the case when it was dangerous to openly confess Christ. And because of the follower’s life, it will become evident who the admirers are, for the admirers will become agitated with him. Even that these words are presented as they are here will disturb many – but then they must likewise belong to the admirers.

07 May 2007

Plantinga and the Problem of Evil

I just finished taking Philosophy 364, Metaphysics. For my term paper, I wrote on the subject of Alvin Plantinga's Free Will Defense to the so-called logical problem of evil. Plantinga's solution is accepted by most philosophers, theists and atheists alike, as having solved the problem. My metaphysics professor disagrees that that's the case. So for my term paper I downloaded one of his articles and argued against him.

----------------------------------------------------------------

Plantinga's Free Will Defense

Alvin Plantinga’s Free Will Defense has been widely celebrated as a workable solution to the logical problem of evil (as set forward most notably by J.L. Mackie). Plantinga’s Defense is remarkable in that it is accepted by most philosophers, theistic and atheistic alike, as having solved the problem. Plantinga’s solution is, however, not universally accepted. There remain many critics who argue that Plantinga does not offer an adequate solution to the logical problem of evil. In this paper I will briefly outline Plantinga’s strategy for solving the problem. I will consider one objection to the Free Will Defense raised by Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky and I will suggest possible rebuttals to this objection.

Plantinga’s Free Will Defense

Plantinga begins with a short introduction to the problem. “Many philosophers…have argued that there is a contradiction involved in asserting, as the theist does, that God is perfectly good, omnipotent (i.e. all-powerful), and omniscient (i.e. all-knowing) on the one hand, and, on the other, that there is evil” (Plantinga 11, emphasis in the original). J.L. Mackie, for instance, makes this sort of claim: "In its simplest form the problem is this: God is omnipotent; God is wholly good; and yet evil exists. There seems to be some contradiction between these three propositions, so that if any two of them were true the third would be false. But at the same time all three are essential parts of most theological positions: the theologian, it seems, at once must adhere and cannot consistently adhere to all three" (Mackie 216, emphasis in the original). What is striking about this suggestion is that the argument Mackie sets forth concludes that the theist is not merely erroneous in believing both that an all-good, all-powerful God exists and that there is evil—but that he is positively illogical in doing so. Mackie, if successful, wishes to establish that it is logically impossible to believe that both exist, and that, therefore, theistic belief is irrational.

Plantinga rebuts this claim by pointing out that the set of propositions:

(1) God is wholly good
(2) God is all-powerful
and
(3) Evil exists

(hereafter called set A) is neither explicitly contradictory (i.e. no one proposition is the denial of any other proposition) nor formally contradictory (i.e. no logical rule will produce a contradiction from set A alone) (Plantinga 12-14). Perhaps, then, set A is implicitly contradictory—perhaps there is some necessarily true proposition that, when added to set A, will yield a contradiction. But Plantinga thinks that atheists have failed to advance a necessarily true proposition that will do this work. The conclusion, he thinks, is that while set A is often asserted to be contradictory, it has not successfully been shown to be (Plantinga 23).

Plantinga then sets about constructing a Free Will Defense. He defines his task over against a Free Will Theodicy: whereas the latter wants to show what God’s reason is for permitting evil, the Free Will Defense tries to show what it might be (without arguing whether it is true). The Free Will Defense, then, is less ambitious than a Free Will Theodicy, but also more likely to succeed. The logical problem of evil holds that it is impossible for set A to be true—to defeat the problem the Free Will Defense must only show that set A it is possibly true—not that it is true. “The heart of the Free Will Defense,” Plantinga says, “is the claim that it is possible that God could not have created a universe containing moral good…without creating one that also contained moral evil” (Plantinga 31, emphasis in the original). Note again that Plantinga isn’t arguing that it is the case that God could not have created moral good but no moral evil—he is arguing that it is possible that God could not have done so. So—is it possible that God could not have created just any world?

Plantinga thinks it’s the case that there are possible worlds in which free creatures exist but do no wrong—the pertinent question is, however, whether God could have made such a world (Plantinga 40). It might be the case that it is not possible for God to actualize these worlds due to a condition Plantinga names “transworld depravity.”

Consider, as Plantinga does, the case of Curley, a corrupt city official. God knows that if Curley is offered a bribe, he will freely choose to accept it. Now consider some state of affairs S such that in S Curley is offered—but has not accepted or rejected—a bribe. Obviously there are a great many possible worlds that include S—and in at least one of these Curley is significantly free but does no moral wrong (call such a world W). But “the sad truth about Curley” may be that he suffers from transworld depravity—that is, in any possible world W’ in which Curley is significantly morally free but does no wrong, there is some state of affairs S’ that includes the morally significant act A’ such that if S’ were actual, Curley would go wrong with respect to A’. Let us then return to the situation of the bribe. If S is included in W, then in that possible world, Curley does no wrong, and rejects the bribe—but God could not have actualized that world. If he had, S would be actual, and Curley would have gone wrong and taken the bribe (for remember, God knows that if Curley is offered a bribe, he will freely accept it). But then that world would no longer be W (for W is a world in which Curley does no wrong)—so God cannot actualize W. In addition, God can’t “bring it about” that Curley rejects the bribe, for then Curley would not be significantly morally free with respect to the question of taking or not taking the bribe—and again, God would not have actualized W, because in W Curley is significantly free (Plantinga 46-48). What is crucial about all this is that if Curley suffers from transworld depravity, then it is not within God’s power to actualize any world in which Curley does moral good but no moral wrong. Furthermore, Plantinga thinks that it is possible that everyone suffers from transworld depravity—if that were the case, the price that God would have to pay for creating a world in which humans are significantly free is that they will produce some moral evil. And if that’s the case—if that’s even possible—then it is possible that God could not have created a world with moral good but no moral evil (Plantinga 46-49).

But surely God could have avoided this difficulty altogether: he could have created different people, ones that did not suffer from transworld depravity. It seems that if he had done that, he might have been able to create a world with moral good but no moral evil (Plantinga 49). Returning to Curley, recall that because of Curley’s transworld depravity, God could not have created any world in which Curley is significantly free but does no wrong. Plantinga thinks that it may be the case that transworld depravity is part of Curley’s essence, in consequence of which God cannot create a world with a free Curley, but without moral evil (for to instantiate Curley’s essence is to instantiate an essence that includes transworld depravity). Plantinga supposes further that it is possible that every “creaturely essence” (i.e. every essence that is not God) has the property of transworld depravity. If that were the case, then it would not be possible to create a world with moral good but no moral evil, no matter which creatures were a part of it (Plantinga 49-53). Remember, Plantinga is not trying to establish that every creaturely essence does suffer from transworld depravity—only that it is possible that they do. If that is even possible then, following Plantinga’s argument, set A is not impossible, and Plantinga has solved the logical problem of evil.

Objections to Plantinga’s Free Will Defense

In “Plantinga and the Problem of Evil,” Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky deny that Plantinga’s Free Will Defense solves the logical problem of evil. They begin by discussing the difference Plantinga draws between strong and weak actualization. Strongly actualizing a state of affairs means being the cause of that state of affairs—“So if God were to strongly actualize that human beings choose to do something, then God would be causing them to do it, and Plantinga believes this is incompatible with freedom” (Geirsson and Losonsky 109). This means that God cannot strongly actualize a totality that includes free actions. To do so would mean that a person would both be free and not free. God can, however, weakly actualize a world that contains free beings. He does so “by strongly actualizing T, a subset of world W that includes beings that have the potential to act freely,” and what is significant about this is that “the free beings complete the creation of W with their free acts” (Geirsson and Losonsky 110). Having differentiated between strong and weak actualization, Geirsson and Losonsky assert that Plantinga’s task is to show that

(4) “It is possible that God is omnipotent and it was not within God’s power to strongly or weakly actualize a world with moral good but no moral evil” (Geirsson and Losonsky 110, emphasis added).

Returning again to the case of Curley, the corrupt city official, Geirsson and Losonsky argue that the crucial problem for Plantinga’s task is that although it is clearly not possible for God to strongly actualize a world in which Curley does not take the bribe (which would cancel Curley’s freedom), “it does not follow that it is not possible that God has the power to weakly actualize a world in which Curley does not take the bribe” (Geirsson and Losonsky 111). Since God knows all “counterfactuals of freedom,” God knows in which worlds Curley will complete the creation by taking the bribe, and in which he will complete it by rejecting the bribe. Nothing prevents God from strongly actualizing those world subsets in which Curley will go on to freely choose not to take the bribe. And if that is so in the case of the bribe, it is also true for other moral decisions of Curley’s—indeed, if God knows all counterfactuals of freedom, then God can actualize that world segment in which Curley completes God’s creation by taking no morally wrong actions at all.

Obviously, this argument can be extended to include people other than Curley: “God surveys all the possible worlds, including how they are completed by free beings, and has a choice between worlds that are completed by free beings in such a way that there is no moral evil and worlds that are completed by free beings in such a way that there is moral evil” (Geirsson and Losonsky 113). If God has that choice, the logical problem remains, Geirsson and Losonsky argue, because a perfect God would have weakly actualized one of the worlds completed without moral evil. Thus there remains inconsistency between moral evil on the one hand and a perfect God on the other, such that the two are logically incompatible.

Free Will Defense Reply

The trouble seems to be that the problem of transworld depravity will not be affected by whether God weakly or strongly actualizes some possible world. Recall that Plantinga thinks that if a person P suffers from transworld depravity, then for any world W such that P is significantly free in W and such that P does no wrong in W there is some state of affairs S in W that includes a morally significant act A such that if S were actual P would go wrong with respect to A (Plantinga 48).

Let us reconsider the case of Curley, the corrupt city official. Geirsson and Losonsky argue that God could have surveyed all possible worlds and found a possible world in which Curley freely rejected the bribe. They argue that God could have weakly actualized that world—Curley would then have completed God’s creation (in part) by rejecting the bribe. But how will this be possible if Curley suffers from transworld depravity? Clearly there is some possible world in which Curley freely rejects the bribe—there is even at least one in which he does no moral wrong at all (and Plantinga acknowledges this). But if God actualizes that world, even weakly, Curley’s transworld depravity will be “triggered”: his S will be actual and he will go wrong with respect to his A. It may turn out that accepting the bribe isn’t Curley’s act A—it could turn out that quarreling with his wife is Curley’s A or perhaps his A is cheating on his income taxes. It hardly matters. Because even if Curley freely rejects the bribe, Curley will still go wrong with respect to some morally significant act (namely, his A), and it will not be the case that he completes God’s creation by doing no moral wrong. And then that world will not be W because Curley does no moral wrong in W; it will turn out that God did not actualize W after all. Hence it is not within God’s power to actualize W, even weakly, for to do so will trigger Curley’s transworld depravity in such a way that that world will turn out not to be W at all.

Geirsson and Losonsky are absolutely right that God can survey all possible worlds and identify some one in which all people do only moral good, and no moral evil. Furthermore, they are right in asserting that the differentiation between strong and weak actualization implies the refinement of Plantinga’s task as they stated it in (4). But they have argued that while it may be true that God cannot strongly actualize a world without moral evil, he can weakly actualize one. It is not clear, however, how such weak actualization defeats the problem of transworld depravity. To do so, it will be necessary to show how God could actualize a world that would not trigger the problem of transworld depravity. Unfortunately, weak actualization does not seem to accomplish this. It remains possible, then, that God could not have actualized a world—strongly or weakly—with moral good but no moral evil.






Works Cited
Geirsson, Heimir and Losonsky, Michael. “Plantinga and the Problem of Evil.” Proceedings of the XXI World Congress of Philosophy (2006). 109-113.

Mackie, J.L. “Evil and Omnipotence.” Mind 64 (1955): 200-212. Rpt. in Beginning Metaphysics. Ed. Geirsson, Heirmir; Losonsky, Michael. Massachets: Blackwell Publishers Ltd., 1998. 215-226.

Plantinga, Alvin. God, Freedom, and Evil. Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 1974.

22 March 2007

Sermons

For those of you who've asked for copies of the messages I gave last summer, you can find the sound files and powerpoint slides here:

060607--First John--Sermon 1.ppt
060611 First John Sermon 1.wma
060613--First John--Sermon 2.ppt
060618 First John Sermon 2.wma

28 January 2007

The Casbah-Rocking light is now lit throughout the ship.

Imagine this: you're cooped up on a ship with 5,500 other people. There's nowhere to go, and not much of anything to do. Every day is the same grinding routine of work and sleep. Imagine what you might do to entertain yourself. Such is the condition of sailors on a aircraft carrier on a 6-month cruise. I've often told people that when I was on cruise I'd do just about anything to amuse myself. Well, thanks to modern technology, I don't have to describe the qcky misadventures I got myself into. I can just show you what happens when board sailors get a hold of a video camera and video editing software.

http://youtube.com/watch?v=QEkYqL9n7vo

http://youtube.com/watch?v=DqaWdkdFb3Y&NR

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=puVmKfCwb4M

Enjoy!